Studies in Phenomenology



Article/Publication Details
Views: 3822


MUNDUS, PAX, COMMUNITAS: ON DIFFERENT MEANINGS OF THE WORLD-CONCEPT IN RUSSIAN LANGUAGE

Title in the language of publication: МИР, ПОКОЙ, ОБЩИНА: О ВЗАИМОСВЯЗИ ЗНАЧЕНИЙ ПОНЯТИЯ «МИР» В РУССКОМ ЯЗЫКЕ
Author: ALEXANDER FROLOV
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 7, №2 (2018),  297-311
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2018-7-2-297-311 PDF (Downloads: 2758)

Abstract
In this article we have tried to trace the correlations between different meanings of the world-concept in Russian language. The problematic point is that the same Russian word (“mir”) has three meanings separated in other Indo-European languages (mundus, pax, communitas). The analysis of this issue is preceded by an exposition of the world-problem in modern philosophy, with an emphasis put on the so-called “cosmological difference” introduced by Eugen Fink. It turned out that both for Russian and other languages, the core of the considered concept is a habitable space which the order, agreement and concordance between people take place in. Thus, such aspects of the world as community (communitas) and as peace, harmony (pax) intersect here. Further, the derived meanings of the concept of communitas were considered, starting from the peasant and Church community to the “historical world” and the “secular world” (in its Christian interpretation). In conclusion, we turned to the experience of some special sentiments having a cosmological value. First of all, it is the unique experience of the universal harmony (harmonia mundi), i.e. the experience of the world as peace (eirēnē, pax) in cosmological perspective. In addition, existential-practical conditions of the possibility of such experience (location, disposition and care) were considered. We also drew attention to some natural and social factors that prevent participation in the experience of the cosmological harmony. As a problematization of such experience, it was emphasized that from the theological standpoint the idea of the world, as the whole, can be realized only in the eschatological outlook, since the world in its present state is split, subjected to disorganization and only partly serves as an image (“icon”) reminding of its Creator.

Key words
World, cosmos, peace, concordance, Heidegger, Fink, Bibikhin.

References

  • Antonii, mitropolit Surozhskii. (2012). Uverennost’ v veshchakh nevidimykh. Poslednie besedy (2000-2001) [Confidence in the Things Invisible. The Last Conversations (2000-2001)]. Moscow: Nikeya. (in Russian).
  • Afanas’eva, N. (2013). Mir mirovi podazhd’, Chelovekolyubche! [Let Peace be upon the World, oh the Lover of Mankind!]. Parfenon segodnya: pravoslavnyi zhurnal [Parthenon Today: Orthodox Magazine], 5 (2), 2-7. (in Russian).
  • Batkin, L. (1978). Ital’yanskie gumanisty: stil’ zhizni i stil’ myshleniya [Italian Humanists: Style of Life, Style of Thinking]. Moscow: Science. (in Russian).
  • Bibikhin, V. (1995). Mir [The World]. Tomsk: Vodolei. (in Russian).
  • Dil’tei, V. (2004). Postroenie istoricheskogo mira v naukakh o dukhe [The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences]. In Sobranie sochinenii v shesti tomakh. T. 3 [Collected Works in 6 Volumes, Vol. 3]. Moscow: Tri kvadrata, 2004. (in Russian).
  • Fink, E. (1977). Sein und Mensch: Vom Wesen der ontologischen Erfahrung. Freiburg: Karl Alber Verlag.
  • Gabriel, M. (2013). Warum es die Welt nicht gibt. Berlin: Ullstein.
  • Grigorii Bogoslov, Svt. (1912). Tvoreniya. T. 1 [Works, Vol. 1]. St Petersburg: Tipografiya P.P. Soikina. (in Russian).
  • Gurevich, A. (1984). Kategorii srednevekovoi kul’tury [Categories of the Middle Age Culture]. Moscow: Nauka. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (2004). Krizis evropeiskikh nauk i transtsendental’naya fenomenologiya [The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology]. St Petersburg: Izdatel’stvo «Vladimir Dal’». (in Russian).
  • Ionkus, D. (2004). Problema mira v fenomenologii E. Finka [The Problem of the World in E. Fink’s Phenomenology]. Topos, 9 (2), 51-61. (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (1993). Veshch’ [The Thing]. In M. Khaidegger, Vremya i bytie [Time and Being] (316-326). Мoscow: Respublika. (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (1997). Bytie i vremya [Being and Time]. Moscow: Ad Marginem. (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (1998). O sushchestve osnovaniya. [On the Essence of Ground]. In Filosofiya v poiskakh ontologii: Sbornik trudov Samarskoi gumanitarnoi akademii, vyp. 5 [Philosophy in Search of Ontology. Collection of the Works of Samara Humanitarian Academy, Issue 5] (78-130). Samara: Izdatel’stvo SamGA. (in Russian).
  • Marion, Zh.-L. (2014). Nasyshchennyi fenomen [The Saturated Phenomenon]. In S. Sholokhova & A. Yampol’skaya (Eds.), (Post)fenomenologiya: novaya fenomenologiya vo Frantsii i za ee predelami [(Post)phenomenology: New Phenomenology in France and Beyond] (63-99). Moscow: Akademicheskii proekt. (in Russian).
  • Merlo-Ponti, M. (1999). Fenomenologiya vospriyatiya [Phenomenology of Perception]. St Petersburg: Yuventa, Nauka. (in Russian).
  • Ortega-i-Gasset, J. (1991). Chto takoe filosofiya? [What is Philosophy?]. Moscow: Nauka. (in Russian).
  • Stepanov, Yu. (2004). Mir [The Universe]. In Konstanty: Slovar’ russkoi kultury [The Constants: A Dictionary of Russian Culture] (86-126). Moscow: Akademicheskii proekt. (in Russian).

Article/Publication Details
Views: 3307


THE CONCEPTIONS OF THE WORLD IN THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT AND FUNDAMENTAL ONTOLOGY OF HEIDEGGER

Title in the language of publication: КОНЦЕПЦИИ МИРА В КРИТИЧЕСКОЙ ФИЛОСОФИИ КАНТА И ФУНДАМЕНТАЛЬНОЙ ОНТОЛОГИИ ХАЙДЕГЕГРА
Author: ANDREI PATKUL
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 7, №2 (2018),  273-296
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2018-7-2-273-296 PDF (Downloads: 3045)

Abstract
The goal of the article is, one the one hand, to show the concrete correlation between the phenomenological conception of the world in Heidegger’s fundamental ontology and its conception in the critical philosophy of Kant, insofar such philosophy could be treated as one of the significant predecessors of Heidegger’s understanding of the world. On the other hand, this explication allows us to analyze the limits and the borders of Heidegger’s phenomenological conception of the world. In order to achieve such goal, the following tasks were undertaken by me: (1) the reconstruction of the phenomenological conception of the world in Heidegger’s fundamental ontology at two levels (i.e. (a) the world as wholeness of involvement and (b) the world as the direction of the transcendence)); (2) the reconstruction of Kant’s cosmological concept of the world made from the perspective of the interpretation of this concept given by Heidegger; (3) detection of the continuity and divergence between Kant’s cosmological concept of the world and its phenomenological conception posed by Heidegger in light of Kant’s concept of the transcendental ideal. As result, I would like to pose and defend the following theses. (1) Heidegger primarily treats the world as a priori condition of the possibility of the wholeness of involvement, and yet, more fundamentally it is treated as the direction for the transcendence of human Dasein. Thus, being understood as such direction, it represents universal horizon of the existent possibilities. (2) Kant characterizes the world as an idea of reason, namely, as the totality of appearances, being formed on the bases of the universal hypothetic synthesis of the unconditional one. Herewith, Kant’s cosmological concept of the world ought to be distinguished from his concept of the moral world. (3) Both Kant and Heidegger understand the world as the totality a priori, which in every case differently presupposes the presence of the human being. (4) The concept of the world as the direction of the transcendence posed by Heidegger has the formal functions similar to those, which are ascribed by Kant to the concept of the sum-total of all possibilities, consequently, not to the world, as the totality of appearances, but to the totality of all objects of thought altogether (to the transcendental ideal). Thereupon, Heidegger believes that whole definition of the Kant’s cosmological concept of the world can be achieved only from the perspective of the transcendental ideal. (5) Heidegger tries to overcome the limitation of Kant’s theory of the world as present being by understanding it as the condition for possibility of that-which-is as ready-at-hand. For Heidegger it is also a way to manifest the ontological foundation common both for Kant’s cosmological and moral concepts of the world.

Key words
World, totality of appearances, involvement, direction of transcendence, transcendental ideal, the sum-total of all possibilities, Kant, Heidegger.

References

  • Dastur, F. (1986). La Constitution Ekstatique-Horizontale de la Temporalité chez Heidegger. Heidegger Studies, 2, 97-109.
  • Heidegger, M. (1976). Metaphysische Anfangsründe der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz (GA 26). Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1996). Einleitung in die Philosophie (GA 27). Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Hinsch, W. (1985). Die Unendlichkeit der Welt in der kritischen Philosophie Kants. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 39(3), 383-409.
  • Ionkus, D. (2004). Problema mira v filosofii Eugena Finka [The Problem of the World in the Philosophy of Eugene Fink]. Topos, 2(9), 51-61. (in Russian).
  • Kant, I. (1964). Kritika chistogo razuma [Critique of Pure Reason]. In Sobranie sochinenii v shesti tomakh. T. 3 [Collected Works in 6 Volumes, Vol. 3]. Moscow: Mysl’. (in Russian).
  • Kant, I. (1994). Antropologiya s pragmaticheskoi tochki zreniya [Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View]. In Sobranie sochinenii v vos’mi tomakh. T. 7 [Collected Works in 8 Volumes, Vol. 7]. Moscow: Izdatel’stvo «Choro». (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (1997). Bytie i vremya [Being and Time]. Moscow: Ad Marginem. (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (1998). O sushchestve osnovaniya. [On the Essence of Ground]. In Filosofiya v poiskakh ontologii: Sbornik trudov Samarskoi gumanitarnoi akademii, vyp. 5 [Philosophy in Search of Ontology. Collection of the Works of Samara Humanitarian Academy, Issue 5] (78-130). Samara: Izdatel’stvo SamGA. (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (2013). Osnovnye ponyatiya metafiziki. Mir — konechnost’ — odinochestvo [Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude]. St Petersburg: Vladimir Dal’. (in Russian).
  • Strasser, S. (1976). Der Begriff der Welt in der phänomenologischen Philosophie. Phänomenologische Forschungen, 3, 151-179.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 4069


REVISTING HUSSERL’S ACCOUNT OF LANGUAGE IN LOGICAL INVESTIGATIONS

Title in the language of publication: REVISTING HUSSERL’S ACCOUNT OF LANGUAGE IN LOGICAL INVESTIGATIONS
Author: PETR URBAN
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 7, №2 (2018),  263-272
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2018-7-2-263-272 PDF (Downloads: 2871)

Abstract
The main aim of this paper is to revisit and reassess the account of language at the origins of Husserl’s phenomenology specifically focusing on Logical Investigations. I would like to argue that there is an ambivalence in Husserl’s discussion of language in Logical Investigations: on the one hand, Husserl is concerned with language as one of the most important symbolic systems and a requisite for scientific knowledge, and he emphasizes the role of linguistic discussions as the philosophically indispensable preparations for constructing pure logic; on the other hand, he applies the idea of the fundamental distinction between the realm of ideal and real being to his views of logic, science and language, which finally causes him to interpret the relation between logic, science and language as the inessential one. The paper begins with discussing Husserl’s view of symbolic methods and sign systems in Prolegomena. The second section is focused on the idea of the necessity of linguistic investigations for pure logic presented in the Introduction to the second volume of Logical Investigations. In the final section I make an analysis of the 4th Logical investigation with the special emphasis put on the idea of pure logical grammar.

Key words
Functions of language, symbolic thought, pure grammar, phenomenology, early Husserl, linguistic investigations, theory of science.

References

  • Byrne, T. (2017a). Husserl’s Early Semiotics and Number Signs: Philosophy of Arithmetic through the Lens of “On the Logic of Signs (Semiotic)”. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 48 (4), 287-303.
  • Byrne, T. (2017b). Surrogates and Empty Intentions: Husserl’s “On the Logic of Signs” as the Blueprint for his First Logical Investigation. Husserl Studies, 33 (3), 211-227.
  • Derrida, J. (1978). Edmund Husserl’s Origin of Geometry: An Introduction. Stony Brook, New York: Nicolas Hays.
  • Fisette, D. (2003). Husserl’s Programme of a Wissenschaftslehre in the “Logical Investigations”. In D. Fisette (Ed.), Husserl’s Logical Investigation Reconsidered (33-57). Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Husserl, E. (1994a). Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics. New York: Springer.
  • Husserl, E. (1994b). On a Logic of Sings (Semiotic). In Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics (12-19). New York: Springer.
  • Husserl, E. (2001a). Logical Investigations. Volume I. London, New York: Routledge.
  • Husserl, E. (2001b). Logical Investigations. Volume II. London, New York: Routledge.
  • Husserl, E. (2003). Philosophy of Arithmetic. Psychological and Logical Investigations with Supplementary Texts from 1887-1901. New York: Springer.
  • Mensch, J. (1981). The Question of Being in Husserl’s Logical Investigations. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Mensch, J. (2003). Real and Ideal Determination in Husserl’s Sixth Logical Investigation. In D. Fisette (Ed.), Husserl’s Logical Investigations Reconsidered (211-222). Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Schmit, R. (1992). Die Idee der logischen Grammatik bei Husserl: Eine begriffsgeschichtliche Betrachtung. Husserl Studies, 9 (1), 31-49.