- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5440
EUGEN FINK'S KANT-INTERPRETATION
Title in the language of publication: | EUGEN FINKS KANT-INTERPRETATION |
Author: | Yusuke Ikeda |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  154-185 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-154-185 | PDF (Downloads: 4307) |
Abstract
In this paper I outline main theses of Fink's phenomenological interpretation of Kantian transcendental
philosophy. My aim is to clarify how and to what extent Kant's philosophy determines Fink's
«phenomenology of enworlding [Verweltlichung]». First, I show the very starting point and original
motivations of Fink's interpretation of Kant. I proceed by examining the contexts in which Fink refers
to Kant's arguments in the Antinomy of Pure Reason and showing that in these contexts Fink is dealing
with a specific philosophical issue, namely, how to conceive of the totality of the «absolute stream of
lived experiencing [der absolute Erlebnisstrom]», an issue the late Husserl struggled with. To solve this
difficult problem, one needs, according to Fink, to commit oneself to an ontological reflection on the
very difference between the intra-temporal entities and time itself. Fink seeks to find a clue to resolve
this problem in Kant's cosmological antinomy: in effect, the latter is based, for Fink, on Kant's profound
distinction between the intra-worldly entities and the world as such («cosmological difference»).
Second, I study Fink's criticism of Kant and how he argues for its phenomenological validity. Further,
I show that Fink does not accept Kant's «Doctrine of Transcendental Idealism» which offers, according
to Kant, the key for the solution to the cosmological antinomy or transcendental illusion. In other
words, Fink refuses the Kantian claim according to which the source of the antinomy is nothing but
pure reason as the upper faculty of dialectical reasoning. Now, it is on the basis of his phenomenological
idealism, which defends an enworlded conception of transcendental subjectivity, that Fink criticizes
Kant's account of a worldles subjectivity. Thus, third, I sketch Fink's phenomenology of enworlding as
well as his new solution for the cosmological antinomy. Fink based the very origin of the transcendental
illusion of cosmological antinomy on the phenomenon of the world in its specific mode of appearing,
which he calls «withdrawing [Entzug or “Entziehung”]». By examining his description of it, one can
easily show and justify the profound difference Fink's phenomenological interpretations of Kant's transcendental
philosophy (who is exposing his cosmological phenomenology) and Heidegger's (whose
goal is to found his hermeneutico-phenomenological idea of fundamental ontology), even if they both
agree that the relevance of Kant's philosophy as a whole does not lie in its epistemology but in its providing
a new foundation for metaphysics. I conclude by stating that Fink's cosmological phenomenology,
which is often criticized because of its speculative character, is based not so much on Hegel's idea
of dialectic, as on Kant's (i.e., as profoundly revised by Fink's phenomenology).
Key words
World, transcendental idealism, metaphysics, totality, cosmological dialectic (antinomy), transcendental illusion, phenomenology of enworlding.
References
- Bernet, R. (2004). Conscience et Existence — Perspectives phénoménologiques. Paris: PUF.
- Bernet, R. (2012). Phänomenologische Begriffe der Unwahrheit bei Husserl und Heidegger. In R. Bernet, A. Denker, & H. Zaborowski (Eds.), Heidegger-Jahrbuch 6. Heidegger und Husserl (108–130). Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- Bruzina, R. (2006). Hinter der ausgeschriebenen Finkschen Meditation: Meontik-Pädagogik. In A. Böhmer (Ed.), Eugen Fink. Sozialphilosophie, Anthropologie, Kosmologie, Pädagogik, Methodik (193–219). Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann.
- Crowell, S. G. (2001). Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning. Paths toward Transcenental Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
- Figal, G. (2006). Gegenständlichkeit. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
- Fink, E. (1957). Zur ontologischen Frühgeschichte von Raum, Zeit, Bewegung. Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Fink, E. (1959). Alles und Nichts Ein Umweg zur Philosophie. Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Fink, E. (1966). Studien zur Phänomenologie 1930–1939. Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Fink, E. (1978). Grundfragen der systematischen Pädagogik. Freiburg: Rombach Freiburg.
- Fink, E. (1985). Einleitung in die Philosophie. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.
- Fink, E. (1988a). VI.Cartesianische Meditation. Teil 1. Die Idee einer transzendentalen Methodenkehre (Hua II/1). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
- Fink, E. (1988b). VI.Cartesianische Meditation. Teil 2. Ergänzungsband (Hua II/2). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
- Fink, E. (1990). Welt und Endlichkeit. Würzburg: Königs & Neumann.
- Fink, E. (2006). Die Doktorarbeit und erste Assistenzjahre bei Husserl (GA 3/1). Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- Fink, E. (2008). Die Bernauer Manuskripte Cartesianische Meditationen und System der phänomenologischen Philosophie (GA 3/2). Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- Fink, E. (2011). Epilegomena zu Immanuel Kants «Kritik der reinen Vernunft» (GA 13/1–3). München, Freiburg: Karl Alber.
- Hegel, G.W. F. (1989). Phänomenologie des Geistes. Frankfurt a. Main: Suhrkamp.
- Heidegger, M. (1976). Wegmarken. Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1977). Sein und Zeit. Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1983). Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt-Endlichkeit-Einsamkeit. Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1984). Die Frage nach dem Ding. Zu Kants Lehre von den transzendentalen Grundsätze. Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1985). Unterwegs zur Sprache. Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1991). Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (GA 3). Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M., & Fink, E. (1970). Heraklit, Seminar, Wintersemester 1966/1967. Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Husserl, E. (1950). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge (Hua I). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1954). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaft und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie (Hua VI). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (2002a.). Logische Untersuchungen. Ergänzungsband Erster Teil. Entwürfe zur Umarbeitung der VI. Untersuchung und zur Vorrede für die Neuauflage der Logischen Untersuchungen (Sommer 1913) (Hua XX/1). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Husserl, E. (2002b). Zur phänomenologischen Reduktion. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1926–1935) (Hua XXXIV). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
- Husserl, E. (2003). Transzendentaler Idealismus. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1921) (Hua XXXVI). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Ikeda, Y. (2014). Transzendentaler Schein und phänomenologische Ursprünglichkeit — Welterfahrung bei Husserl und Fink. Horizon, 3(1), 64–98.
- Ikeda, Y. (2015). L'événementialité du phénomène selon Neue Phänomenologie in Frankreich. Revue internationale Michel Henry, 6, 177–202.
- Jaran, F. (2010). La métaphysique du Dasein. Heidegger et la possibilité de la métaphysique (1927–1930). Bucarest: Zeta books.
- Kant, I. (1781/87). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Riga: Hartknoch.
- Kant, I. (1922). Kant's Briefwechsel Band III 1795–1803. Berlin, Leipzig: de Gruyter.
- Lazzari, R. (2011). Weltfrage und kosmologische Interpretation von Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft bei Eugen Fink. In C. Nielsen, & H.-R. Sepp (Eds.), Welt denken. Annährung an die Kosmologie Eugen Finks (38–56). München, Freiburg: Karl Alber.
- Tengelyi, L. (2014). Welt und Unendlichkeit. Zum Problem phänomenologischer Metaphysik. Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5836
SELF AND BODY. HUSSERL'S AND LEVINAS' DEBATES WITH THE GERMAN IDEALISM
Title in the language of publication: | SELBST UND LEIB. AUSEINANDERSETZUNGEN MIT DEM DEUTSCHEN IDEALISMUS BEI HUSSERL UND LEVINAS |
Author: | Karel Novotný |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  139-153 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-139-153 | PDF (Downloads: 4180) |
Abstract
The article follows some lines of thought in Husserl and Levinas, their texts namely in which
the close relation between the self and body should be grasped as one of the topics where the
idealistic approach to subjectivity is abandoned. Already in Husserl one can find reflections on
the significant affective-bodily dimension of the transcendental subjectivity itself which is one of
the ways he overcomes the classical dualistic modern philosophical tradition. Levinas went even
further in his critical debate with this classical thinking and — in certain continuity with Husserl
— gave a new account of the affective-bodily constitution of the singularity of human subjectivity.
In both cases the singularisation of the self pass through an intersubjective constitution of
the own body that is an event for Levinas that precedes an egoic consciousness. But in both cases
there is a problem that the theories cannot solve: the body as mine has to be presupposed. There is
a certain self-preceding of the lived body that seems to function as a basis for the self-awareness
in the lived experiences, a factical basis that not only relativizes an idealistic point of departure in
a pure I but also destabilize any attempt to build a system upon the phenomenological accounts of
the relation between the body and the self. The transcendental-phenomenological reductions, the
genetic ones in Husserl, and the ethical ones in Levinas, lead to more (Levinas) or less (Husserl)
radical divergences with the projects of totalizing systems in the style of the German idealism.
Key words
Subjectivity, self, corporeal / Leib, body / Körper, affectivity, sensuousness, singularity.
References
- Franck, D. (1981). Chair et corps. Sur la phénoménologie de Husserl. Paris: Minuit.
- Husserl, E. (1952). Ideen zu reiner Phänomenologie und phänomenologischer Philosophie (Hua XV). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Zweiter Teil (1921–28) (Hua XIV). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil (1929–35) (Hua XV). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (2008). Lebenswelt. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil (1929–35) (Hua XXXIX). Dodrecht: Springer.
- Levinas, E. (1989). Humanismus des anderen Menschen. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
- Levinas, E. (1997). Vom Sein zum Seienden. Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- Levinas, E. (1998). Jenseits des Seins oder anders als Sein geschieht. Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- Lohmar, D. (2009). Eine Geschichte des Ich bei Husserl. Mit Bemerkungen zum Ur-Ich in Husserls späten Zeitmanuskripten. In M. Pfeiffer, & S. Rapic (Eds.), Das Selbst und sein Anderes: Festschrift für Klaus Erich Kaehler (162–181). Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.
- Tengelyi, L. (2014). Expérience de la singularité. Paris: Hermann.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5835
«BEING OUTSIDE-ITSELF» IN SCHELLING AND HEIDEGGER
Title in the language of publication: | DAS AUßER-SICH-SEIN BEI SCHELLING UND HEIDEGGER |
Author: | Andrei Patkul |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  121-138 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-121-138 | PDF (Downloads: 4447) |
Abstract
The author of the article framed the question of the possible relevance of the treatment of the
Schelling's philosophy in the context of a phenomenological one. Thereby, he points its problematic
character, referencing Husserl's treatment of German idealism after Kant (including the
thought of Schelling) as the romantic idealism. At the same time, he also states the influence of
Schelling on the few phenomenologists who made their careers after Husserl. The article's author
reviews the concept of the «being outside-itself» or «ecstasy» in Schelling and Heidegger (as one
of the phenomenologists) for the further concretization of the theme. The ecstasy in Schelling is
the new name for the idealistic intellectual intuition, by which a singular subject loses its own
position as subject and thereby gets to the position of the absolute subject. The absolute subject is
one which cannot be an object already. Schelling identifies the ecstasy understood in this way with
the wondering as philosophical initiation in Ancient Greece. Such ecstasy leads to unknowing
knowledge in Schelling's words. The concept of being outside-itself means the structural element
of being of human Dasein, i.e. of temporality in Heidegger. This philosopher thinks that a human
being is always already outside itself ontologically, before any intuition both sensual and intellectual.
The human subject is not closed in on itself, for then it has to transcend from its immanence
to the outside. It is always outside itself, it is ecstatic. In its ecstasies, it is always in the world,
instead of being inside the world and other people. Heidegger bases his critique of the traditional
metaphysics of the subject on such understanding of the ontological structure of Dasein, i.e.
of the true «subject». In conclusion, the article's author states that the approaches to the problem
of being outside-itself of both mentioned philosophers are in principle, quite different. Schelling
tries to rehabilitate the subjectivity by the reduction of the singular subject to the absolute one.
On the contrary, the finitude of human Dasein is the necessary condition of its being in Heidegger.
The ecstasy is interiorization in Schelling, but it is exteriorization, which has been always already
realized, in Heidegger. However, the author of the article also pinpoints a certain isomorphism of
the treatments of ecstasy in both thinkers. In the different ways they attempt to overcome the crisis
of the understanding of the subject as closed in itself, create the conditions of this isomorphism.
Key words
Being outside-itself, ecstasy, intellectual intuition, wondering, Dasein, temporality, existence, metaphysics, German idealism, phenomenology.
References
- Chernyakov, A. G. (2001). Ontologiya vremeni. Vremya i bytie v filosofii Aristotelya, Gusserlya i Khaideggera. [Ontology of time. Time and being in the philosophy of Aristotle, Husserl and Heidegger]. St Petersburg: St Petersburg School of Religion and Philosophy. (in Russian).
- Heidegger, M. (1976). Wegmarken (GA 9). Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1978). Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik in Ausgang von Leibniz (GA 26). Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1989). Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (GA 24). Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (2013). Zum Ereignis-Denken (GA 73). Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Heinz, M. (1982). Zeitlichkeit und Temporalität. Die Konstruktion der Existenz und die Grundlegung einer temporalen Ontologie im Frühwerk Martin Heideggers. Würzburg, Amsterdam: Königshausen & Neumann.
- Husserl, E. (1956). Erste Philosophie (1923/4). Erste Teil (Hua VII). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Iber, C. (1994). Das Andere der Vernunft als ihr Prinzip. Grundzüge der philosophischen Entwicklung Schellings mit einem Ausblick auf die nachidealistischen Philosophiekonzeptionen Heideggers und Adornos. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter.
- Leinkauf, T. (1998). Schelling als Interpret der philosophischen Tradition. Münster: Lit.
- Ohashi, R. (1975). Ekstase und Gelassenheit: zu Schelling und Heidegger. München.
- Schelling, F. W. J. (1858). Philosophie der Offenbarung. Stuttgart: J. G. Cotta'scher.
- Schelling, F. W. J. (1861). Über die Natur der Philosophie als Wissenschaft. Stuttgart: J. G. Cotta'scher.
- Schelling, F. W. J. (1969). Initia philosophiae universae. Bonn: H. Bouvier u. Co.
- Schelling, F. W. J. (2005) System des transcendentalen Idealismus. Historisch-Kritische Ausgabe. Bd 9. Tbd 1. Stuttgart: Fromann-Holzbog.
- Schulz, W. (1975). Die Vollendung des Deutschen Idealismus in der Spätphilosophie Schellings. Pfullingen: Neske.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 6002
TO THE CONCEPT OF «ALIENATION» IN HUSSERL AND HEGEL
Title in the language of publication: | ZUM BEGRIFF DER ENTFREMDUNG BEI HUSSERL UND HEGEL |
Author: | Mikhail Belousov |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  99-120 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-99-120 | PDF (Downloads: 4425) |
Abstract
The article deals with alienation as a difference between subjectivity and itself. Based on the
comparative analysis of the concept in Phenomenology of Spirit and The Crisis of European Sciences
the study treats the difference as a presupposition underlying both phenomenology and German
Idealism and reveals its heuristicity. The first section explicates the conceptual horizon of the
alienation problem in Phenomenology of Spirit. It is the interpretation of Kantian concept of selfconsciousness
in German Idealism. The article analyzes two aspects of the concept motivating
the interpretation: self-consciousness as a spontaneous act and both as the condition and result of
the synthesis. The second section demonstrates the correlation between these aspects and two dimensions
of alienation in Phenomenology of Spirit: the self-assertion of the subject as object, i.e.
as other for itself, and transition from the subject to a predicate, also treated as the self-assertion
of the one (subject) as other (predicate). So the research shows that Hegel identifies actuality of
the subject with becoming itself as becoming other for itself. In its completeness it appears to be
suspended (not eliminated) alienation. The last section is devoted to alienation as the constitution
of another ego in Crisis and compares Husserlian and Hegelian understanding of the phenomenon.
Unlike Hegel, Husserl discovers irreversibility of alienation, as the difference between ego
and alter ego is not the one between ego and itself. Yet the concepts of the primal I (Ur-Ich) and
temporalization as the difference of the I from itself suggest that the difference between ego and
alter ego is grounded in the one of the I from itself. The heuristicity of the grounding is the suspension
of the adequate evidence principle. The difference of ego from itself in intersubjective and
temporal experience as the fundamental difference is constituted insofar as immediate perception
is slipping away.
Key words
Alienation, phenomenology, German Idealism, consciousness, difference, I, оther.
References
- Fikhte, I. G. (1993). Osnova obshchego naukoucheniya [Foundations of the entire science of konwledge]. In Fikhte, I.G. Sochineniya v dvukh tomakh. Tom 1 [Collected Works in 2 Volumes. Volume 1] (65–337). Moscow: Mifril. (in Russian).
- Hegel, G. W. F. (1978). Die Wissenschaft der Logik. Erster Band. Die objektive Logik. Hamburg: Meiner.
- Hegel, G. W. F. (1987). Phänomenologie des Geistes. Stuttgart: Philip Reclam jun.
- Husserl, E. (1973a). Die Idee der Phänomenologie. Fünf Vorlesungen (Hua II). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973b). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge (Hua I). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1976). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie (Hua VI). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
- Kant, I. (2006a). Kritika chistogo razuma [Critique of Pure Reason]. In Kant I. Sochineniya na nemetskom i russkom yazykakh. Tom II. Chast' 2. 1-e izdanie (A), 1781 [Collected Works on German and Russian languages, Volume 2 (2), 1781]. Moskow: Nauka.
- Kant I. (2006b). Kritika chistogo razuma [Critique of Pure Reason]. In Kant I. Sochineniya na nemetskom i russkom yazykakh. Tom II. Chast' 1. 2-е izdanie (B), 1787 [Collected Works on German and Russian languages, Volume 2(1), 1787]. Moskow: Nauka.
- Shelling, F. V. I. (1987). Sistema transtsendental'nogo idealizma [System of transcendental Idealism]. In Shelling, F. V. I. Sochineniya v dvukh tomakh. Tom 1 [Collected Works in 2 Volumes. Volume 1] (227–489). Moscow: Mysl'. (in Russian).
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5756
ON THE BORDER OF SELF-APPEARANCE. SELF-AFFECTION AND REFLECTION IN THE REMEMBERING IN KANT AND HUSSERL
Title in the language of publication: |
AN DEN GRENZEN DER SELBSTERSCHEINUNG. SELBSTAFFEKTION UND REFLEXION IN DER WIEDERERINNERUNG BEI KANT UND HUSSERL |
Author: | Guillermo Ferrer |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  87-98 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-87-98 | PDF (Downloads: 4226) |
Abstract
In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant points out that the inclusion of the inner representations of
a subject in the form of time does not link them so as to produce the self-consciousness. To this
end, a synthesis of the understanding — by means of the transcendental imagination — that affects
the inner sense is necessary. Therefore the temporal succession of my inner states will appear
to me until I draw implicitly an infinite line which is an image of time representing its succession
on the space, thus inasmuch as I am conscious, at least implicitly, of my activity of the drawing.
Using the example of the peculiar reflection of remembering, I will hypothesize the idea that
a phenomenology of self-consciousness could readopt and renew Kant's theory of self-affection;
however the limits of a phenomenological analysis of the reflection on my past and my past Self
shall be set. Because of these limits, the reflection on my past I is always tainted with «substitutes»
of my life-history, namely fluctuating representations of my experience in the past. Also, in this
respect I am a passive subject facing the spontaneity of my phantasy while I remember myself.
From a phenomenological point of view we can rearrange Kant's theory in this way: by reflection
on my past, the I splits into a remembering-I and a phantasy-I that fills out the horizon of memory
to some extent with substitutes. In this respect my life-history is never given to me without a mediation
of phantasy and imagination.
Key words
Self-affection, reflection, past I, Self, irrevocability, substitutes, phantasy.
References
- Allison, Henry E. (2015). Kant's Transcendental Deduction. An Analytical-Historical Commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Ferrer, G. (2015). Protentionalität und Urimpression. Elemente einer Phänomenologie der Erwartungsintentionen in Husserls Analyse des Zeitbewusstseins. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.
- Husserl, E. (1966). Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Aus Vorlesungs und Forschungsmanuskripten 1918–1926 (Hua XI). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935 (Hua XV). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1980). Phantasie, Bildbewusstsein, Erinnerung. Zur Phänomenologie der anschaulichen Vergegenwärtigungen. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1898–1925) (Hua XXIII). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Kant, I. (1998). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
- Kern, I. (1964). Husserl und Kant. Eine Untersuchung über Husserls Verhältnis zu Kant und zum Neukantianismus. Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Lohmar, D. (2008). Phänomenologie der schwachen Phantasien. Untersuchungen der Psychologie, cognitive Science, Neurologie und Phänomenologie zur Funktion der Phantasie in der Wahrnehmung. Dordrecht: Springer.
- Richir, M. (2000). Phénoménologie en esquisses. Nouvelles fondations. Grenoble: Éditions Jérôme Millon.
- Ricœur, P. (1985). Temps et récit 3: Le temps raconté. Paris: Seuil.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 4921
WHAT IS A PROBLEM?
Title in the language of publication: | WHAT IS A PROBLEM? |
Author: | Andrew Haas |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  71-86 |
Language: | English |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-71-86 | PDF (Downloads: 5305) |
Abstract
What is a problem? What is problematic about any problem whatsoever, philosophical or otherwise?
As the origin of assertion and apodeiction, the problematic suspends the categories of
necessity and contingency, possibility and impossibility. And it is this suspension that is the essence
of the problem, which is why it is so suspenseful. But then, how is the problem problematic?
Only if what is suspended neither comes to presence, nor simply goes out into absence,
that is, if the suspension continues, which continues the problem. But what is problematic about
suspension? As a consideration of language shows, the problem of suspension is the problem of
implication. If being, for example, is merely implied, neither present nor absent, then it is the
suspension of both, at least insofar as it is problematic. And this not only says something about
language; rather, it has ontological implications as well — it speaks of being, and the being of
anything whatsoever. For if being is implied, if that is the problem of being, it is because being is
an implication. Then the being of things like problems is implied as well; or being is in things by
implication. But what does it mean for being to be neither presence nor absence, but an implication?
It means that being is implied in a way that is problematic — before it is necessary, or even
possible. For being's way of being is characterized by suspension — which has implications for
thinking and speaking about being, and about things like problems, even about anything whatsoever.
And this has implications for what being implies, namely, unity and time and aspect.
Key words
Apodeictic, aspect, assertoric, being, implication, problematic, suspension, time, unity.
References
- Aeschylus (1973). Septem Quae Supersunt Tragoedias. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Aristotle (1950). Physica. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Aristotle (1957). Metaphysica. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Benjamin, W. (1991). Gesammelte Schriften. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
- Brooks, C. (1949). The Well Wrought Urn. London: Dobson Books.
- Comrie, B. (1976). Aspect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Derrida, J. (1967). La voix et le phénomène. Paris: PUF.
- Derrida, J. (1972). Ousia et grammè: note sur une note de Sein und Zeit. In Marges de la philosophie. Paris: Minuit.
- Derrida, J. (2001). L'Université sans condition. Paris: Galilée.
- Derrida, J. (2003). Voyous. Paris: Galilée.
- Diels, H. (1960). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Hildesheim: Weidmann.
- Dostoyevsky, F. M. (1864). Zapiski iz podpol'ya [Notes from Underground]. St. Petersburg: Epokha. (in Russian).
- Dostoyevsky, F. M. (1993). Notes from Underground. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
- Frege, G. (1879). Begriffschrift. Halle: Louis Nebert.
- Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Haas, A. (2007a). Being and Implication: On Hegel and the Greeks. Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, 3 (3), 192–210.
- Haas, A. (2007b). The Irony of Heidegger. London: Continuum International Publishing.
- Haas, A. (2014). Notes on Benjamin and Intimacy. Rivista Italiana di Filosofia del Linguaggio, 8 (2), 112–124.
- Haas, A. (2015a). Notes on Time and Aspect. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 23 (4), 504–517. doi: 10.1080/09672559.2014.996245.
- Haas, A. (2015b). The Ambiguity of Being. In Georgakis, T., & Ennis, P. J. (Eds.), Heidegger in the Twenty-First Century (9–22). Dordrecht: Springer. doi: 10.1007/978-94-017-9679-8_2.
- Hegel, G.W.F. (1974). Wissenschaft der Logik I (Bd. V). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
- Hegel, G.W.F. (1970). Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Mit Hegels eigenhändigen Notizen und den mündlichen Zusätzen (Bd. VII). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
- Heidegger, M. (1975). Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (GA 24). Frankfurt a. M.: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1976). Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (GA 21). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1977a). Sein und Zeit (GA 2). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1977b). Phänomenologische Interpretation von Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft (GA 25). Frankfurt a. M.: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1979). Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (GA 20). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1983). Einführung in die Metaphysik (GA 40). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1984). Die Frage nach dem Ding. Zu Kants Lehre von den transzendentalen Grundsätzen (GA 41). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1985a). Phänomenologische Interpretationen zu Aristoteles. Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (GA 61). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1985b). Unterwegs zur Sprache (GA 12). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1989). Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis) (GA 65). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1991). Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (GA 3). Frankfurt a. M.: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1993). Hegel (GA 68). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (1996). Wegmarken (GA 9). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (2002). Grundbegriffe der aristotelischen Philosophie (GA 18). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (2004). Der Begriff der Zeit (GA 64). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Heidegger, M. (2007). Zur Sache des Denkens (GA 14). Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.
- Homer (1920). Homera Operi: Illiad (Vol. II). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Homer (1922). Homera Operi: The Odyssey (Vol. IV). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Husserl, E. (1977). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie (Hua III/1). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesianische Meditationen (Hua I). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Kahn, C. (1979). The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Kahn, C. (2003). The Verb «Be» in Ancient Greek. Indianapolis: Hackett.
- Kant, I. (1900). Gesammelte Schriften. Berlin: Akademie der Wissenschaften.
- Keats, J. (1814–1891). Transcripts of Unpublished Poems, common place book of R. Woodhouse. Boston: Houghton Library, Harvard University.
- McColl, H. (1877). The Calculus of Equivalent Statements and Integration Limits. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 9, 9–20.
- Nietzsche, F. (1967). Also Sprach Zarathustra. Berlin: de Gruyter.
- Palmer, F. (2001). Mood and Modality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Plato (1922). Platonis Opera. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Schmitt, C. (2006). Hamlet or Hecuba. Corvallis: Plutarch Press.
- Sophocles (1990). Fabulae. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Whitehead, A. N., & Russell, B. (1907). Principia Mathematica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Wittgenstein, L. (1921). Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung. In W. Ostwald (Ed.), Annalen der Naturphilosophie (185‑262). Leipzig: Unesma.
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
![]() |
|
|
|
![]() |
|
|
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
Social networks: