- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5683
THE LEFTOVER OF GOOD SENSE:
ON TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE LIGHT OF THE POSTSTRUCTURALIST CRITICISM
Title in the language of publication: |
THE LEFTOVER OF GOOD SENSE: ON TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE LIGHT OF THE POSTSTRUCTURALIST CRITICISM |
Author: | Georgy Chernavin |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  63-70 |
Language: | English |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-63-70 | PDF (Downloads: 4445) |
Abstract
Radically different strategies of interacting with sound common sense, found within three big philosophical
discourses of the 20th century (analytic philosophy, poststructuralism, phenomenology), led
nearly to the impossibility of communication between those discourses. The judgement by Deleuze
concerning Kant's critical philosophy and Husserl's transcendental philosophy seems to be an example
of the failed philosophical dialogue, this time between post-structuralism and (classical as well as modern)
transcendentalism. Deleuze sees in transcendental philosophy the dominance of the twofold instance
of the common sense; the two forms are the sensus communis (which dominated already in Kant)
and the bona mens (which crystallized in the Husserlian Urdoxa). Even if one could agree that the poststructuralist
reading of transcendental philosophy is likely sometimes too rash, it is still helpful. One
can then see that at the center of the research-field of transcendental phenomenology a real nodal point
of paradoxes remains: first of all, the so-called «paradox of human subjectivity» — the relation between
the empirical and the transcendental, which seems to be paradoxical for sound human understanding.
One could contrast here the goal of transcendental research, which consists in sense-building and
sense-enrichment, with the poststructuralist art of the forming, inventing and production of concepts.
The passion for paradoxes, the provocation of the sound human understanding as a motor of thinking
(characteristic of poststructuralism) is still bound to doxa and to the common sense, although it tries to
«turn it inside out». Transcendental philosophy tries rather to take a «step back» from the solidification
of common sense in order to observe the sense-building in statu nascendi.
Key words
Transcendental philosophy, poststructuralism, common sense, doxa, paradox, Husserl, Deleuze.
References
- Deleuze, G. (1969). Logique du sens. Paris: Minuit.
- Deleuze, G. (1990). The Logic of Sense. New York: Athlone Press.
- Deleuze, G. (1995). Difference and Repetition. London, New York: Continuum.
- Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1994). What is Philosophy? New York: Columbia University Press.
- Fink, E. (1988). VI. Cartesianische Meditation. Texte aus dem Nachlass Eugen Finks (1932) mit Anmerkungen und Beilagen aus dem Nachlass Edmund Husserls (1933/34), Teil 1. Die Idee einer transzendentalen Methodenlehre. Husserliana Dokumente (Hua II/1). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Husserl, E. (1954). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaft und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie (Hua VI). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
- Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlaß. Dritter Teil (1929–1935) (Hua XV). Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1993). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Ergänzungsband. Texte aus dem Nachlaß (1934–1937) (Hua XXIX). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Husserl, E. (2002). Zur phänomenologischen Reduktion. Texte aus dem Nachlaß (1926–1935) (Hua XXXIV). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Husserl, E. (2008). Die Lebenswelt. Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer Konstitution. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1916–1937) (Hua XXXIX). Dordrecht: Springer.
- Kant, I. (1975). Kritik der reinen Vernunft ( Bd. III–IV). Frankfurt a. Mein: Suhrkamp.
- Wittgenstein, L. (1979). Schriften: Beiheft (Bd. 3). Frankfurt a. Mein: Suhrkamp.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5653
TRANSCENDENTAL EXPERIENCE AS A THOUGHT EXPERIMENT
Title in the language of publication: | TRANSZENDENTALE ERFAHRUNG ALS GEDANKLICHES EXPERIMENT |
Author: | Alexei Krioukov |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  54-62 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-54-62 | PDF (Downloads: 4160) |
Abstract
In my article I would like to discuss a topic concerning the idea of mental experience as an experiment
in the transcendental philosophy. One of the main problems of the humanities is that one can see
a big difference between two branches of knowledge: human sciences and «exact» sciences. The main
difference consists in the fact that the experimental data of the exact sciences can be verified by other
researchers, but mental data in the mind of one researcher in humanities cannot be repeated in the mind
of another. It allows for the skeptics to say that human sciences and especially philosophy cannot be
real sciences. In opposition to this, the contemporary German philosopher Lambert Wiesing asserts that
in the field of transcendental philosophy we do have something similar to experience in experimental
sciences. It is called the «eidetic variation» (eidetische Variation). Three principles of the method are
of great value. They are: self-reflection, phantasy, and self-clarification. In my article I am going firstly
to clarify the principles of «eidetic variation» in Husserl's phenomenology, and secondly to relate this
to the methods found in German transcendental Idealism. I see three interpretations of the term «eidetic
variation»: as a synonym of the transcendental reduction, as establishing the eidos of a thing and the
transcendental ego itself, and as something that can be held in a phantasy. The same method is used
in German idealism (by Fichte for example). The main outcome of my paper should be, that if we accept
an «eidetic variation» as a transcendental method, we can explain, or at least have an opportunity
to build the abstract category and understand such abstract items as beauty as well as other general
philosophical notions.
Key words
Phenomenology of Husserl, German Idealism, Fichte, eidetic variation, transcendental ego, transcendental reduction.
References
- Fichte, J. G. (1967). Erste Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
- Husserl, E. (1968). Phänomenologische Psychologie. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1925 (Hua IX). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge (Hua I). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1974). Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft. Mit ergänzenden Texten (Hua XVII). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Wiesing, L. (2012). Phänomenologische und experimentelle Ästhetik. In J. Früchtl, & M. Moog-Grünewald (Eds.), Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 6494
HUSSERL'S CRITICISM OF KANT'S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM:
A CLARIFICATION OF PHENOMENOLOGICAL IDEALISM
Title in the language of publication: |
HUSSERLS KRITIK AN KANTS TRANSZENDENTALEM IDEALISMUS: ERÖRTERUNG DES PHÄNOMENOLOGISCHEN IDEALISMUS |
Author: | Dominique Pradelle |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  25-53 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-25-53 | PDF (Downloads: 4530) |
Abstract
This study focuses on the essential difference between Kant's and Husserl's transcendental Idealism.
In fact, Husserl describes in the «Cartesian Meditations» his own ontological thesis as a «transcendental
idealism», in which all sorts of entities have to be constituted by an activity of the transcendental
subjectivity, so that we have to regard pure consciousness as the ontological origin of all entities in the
world. But this study is interested in the two opposite significations of the kantian copernican inversion.
On the one hand, the copernican inversion has the same sense as the phenomenological reduction,
which implies that Husserl can't agree with Kant's presupposition of absolute things in themselves;
on the second hand, it involves a relativistic and anthropologistic orientation, so that the aprioristic
structures of given objects are founded on the universal structures of finite subjectivity, on pure forms
and faculties of human consciousness. At the opposite, Husserl enounces a methodological prescription
for any phenomenological elucidation: it is not allowed to presuppose in phenomenology any given
faculty or given nature of transcendental subjectivity. This prescription has important consequences
on which this study focuses. First the ontological difference between intuitus originarius and intuitus
derivatus, infinite and finite type of intuition, doesn't have any validity: the difference between factual
and rational truths only depends on the essence of the truth itself, and doesn't have its foundation on the
ontological difference between creative and receptive sort of intuition. Secondly, this first thesis admits
an immediate application on the level of subjective constitution of objects: the modality in which an
object appears to the subjectivity doesn't depend on the universal structure of finite subject, but is exclusively
founded on the essence of the object itself, so that it is impossible to consider the aprioristic
constitutive structure as a merely subjective structure. Thirdly, in this transcendental phenomenology
everything has to be constituted by subjectivity: the aprioristic character of the pure forms of sensibility
is not founded on the structure of finite subjectivity, but rather on the essential connection between
sensual material and form; so that it is not allowed to presuppose any facticity of time and space; the
pure forms of sensibility have to be constituted by a special type of synthesis that we have to elucidate
in opposition to other types of higher levels. The profound signification of Husserl's anticopernican
inversion is that the field of transcendental phenomenology consists of the essential form of an eidos
ego, which is «more objective than any objectivity», as Levinas said; and that transcendental phenomenology
is completely dominated by the principium reddendae rationis.
Key words
Copernican inversion, constitution, intuition, Kant, phenomenology, subjectivity, transcendental idealism.
References
- Benoist, J. (2005). Les limites de l'intentionnalité. Paris: Vrin.
- Cohen, H. (1918). Kants Theorie der Erfahrung. Berlin.
- Heidegger, M. (1988). Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929). Frankfurt a. Main: V. Klostermann.
- Husserl, E. (1956). Erste Philosophie (1923/4). Erste Teil (Hua VII). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1959). Erste Philosophie (1923/4). Zweiter Teil (Hua VIII). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973a). Ding und Raum (1907) (Hua XVI). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1973b). Cartesianische Meditationen (1950) (Hua I). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1974). Formale und transzendentale Logik (1929) (Hua XVII). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1976). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie (1935–36) (Hua VI). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1977). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie (1913) (Hua III/1). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1984a). Logische Untersuchungen (1901) (III. Unters.) (Hua XIX/1). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1984b). Logische Untersuchungen (1901) (VI. Unters.) (Hua XIX/2). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (1994a). Brief an Arnold Metzger 4. IX. 1919. In Briefwechsel (IV). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Husserl, E. (1994b). Brief an Pannwitz vom 14. IV. 1937. In Briefwechsel (VII). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Husserl, E. (1999). Erfahrung und Urteil: Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik (1954). Hamburg: Meiner.
- Husserl, E. (2002). Natur und Geist. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1919 (Hua Materialien Vol. IV). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Kant, I. (1781–1787). Kritik der reinen Vernunft (A–B). Riga: Hartknoch.
- Leibniz, F. W. (1974). Monadologie (1714). Paris: Delagrave.
- Levinas, E. (1982). En découvrant l'existence avec Husserl et Heidegger. Paris: Vrin.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 5555
ABOUT SYSTEMATIC HERITAGE OF THE CLASSICAL GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY
(WITH EMPHASIS ON CONCEPT OF REALITY)
Title in the language of publication: |
ZUM SYSTEMATISCHEN ERBE DER KLASSISCHEN DEUTSCHEN PHILOSOPHIE IN DER TRANSZENDENTALEN PHÄNOMENOLOGIE (UNTER BESONDERER BERÜCKSICHTIGUNG DES REALITÄTSBEGRIFFS) |
Author: | Alexander Schnell |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  10-24 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | Research Article |
DOI : 10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-2-10-24 | PDF (Downloads: 4492) |
Abstract
In this paper, I focus on the link between Husserl and Classical German Philosophy on the concept
of reality. The aim of my study is this: explore the phenomenological concept of reality and strengthen
the phenomenological standpoint within the contemporary discussion about «realism». After trying
to outline a general characterization of «reality», I extract the core question of Kant's approach of this
perspective, namely: how is it possible to legitimate the possibility of reality thanks to a priori forms of
understanding? The phenomenological answer is prepared by developing the very essence of Fichte's
and Schelling's discussion on transcendental idealism, on the one hand, and a response to Meillassoux's
critique of «correlationism», on the other. The heart of my demonstration consists then in the attempt
to show that the transcendental constitution of reality — that entails a «new ontology» (Levinas),
characterized both by the «constitution of consciousness» and the «foundation of being» — leans on
Husserl's conception of truth, and especially on the link between the determination of reality and the
apprehension of truth. Furthermore, it brings into play a mediation in which the real determinations
of the constituted being have themselves an effect on this transcendental constitution; and it implies that
the legitimation of this mediation is based on a transcendental («reflexible») reduplication that makes
the possibilisation itself possible. Thus, the concept of reality contains a legitimation of necessity that
recurs both to Schelling and to Fichte (whose influences on Husserl's phenomenology are obviously
systematical rather than historical).
Key words
Reality, transcendentalism, truth, ontology, mediation, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Husserl.
References
- Benoist, J. (2014). Elemente einer realistischen Philosophie. Berlin: Suhrkamp.
- Ferraris, M. (2013). Realismo positive. Torino: Rosenberg & Sellier.
- Gabriel, M. (2015). Fields of Sense: A New Realist Ontology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
- Garcia, T. (2011). Forme et objet. Paris: PUF.
- Harman, G. (2002). Tool-Being. Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects. Chicago: Open Court.
- Holt, E. B. (1912). The New Realism: Cooperative Studies in Philosophy. New York: HardPress Publishing.
- Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935 (Hua XV). Den Haag: Nijhoff.
- Husserl, E. (2006). Späte Texte über Zeitkonstitution (1929–1934) (Hua Materialien Vol. VIII). Dordrecht: Springer.
- Lacan, J. (2011). Le Séminaire. Livre XIX. Paris: Seuil.
- Latour, B. (2012). Enquête sur les modes d'existence. Paris: La Découverte.
- Levinas, E. (2001). En découvrant l'existence avec Husserl et Heidegger. Paris: Vrin.
- Malabou, C. (2014). Avant demain. Épigenèse et rationalité. Paris: PUF.
- Meillassoux, Q. (2008). Nach der Endlichkeit. Berlin: Diaphanes.
- Schelling, F. W. J. (2000). System des transzendentalen Idealismus. Hamburg: F. Meiner.
- Schnell, A. (2007). Husserl et les fondements de la phénoménologie constructive. Grenoble: J. Millon.
- Schnell, A. (2010a). En deçà du sujet. Du temps dans la philosophie transcendantale allemande. Paris: PUF.
- Schnell, A. (2010b). En face de l'extériorité. Levinas et la question de la subjectivité. Paris: Vrin.
- Schnell, A. (2015). La déhiscence du sens. Paris: Hermann.
- Schnell, A. (2016). Wirklichkeitsbilder. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
- Schopenhauer, A. (1977). Preisschrift Über die Grundlage der Moral. München; Wien: Carl Hanser.
- 29 December 2015
Article/Publication Details
Views: 3823
INTRODUCTORY WORD
Title in the language of publication: | VORWORT |
Author: | Alexander Schnell |
Issue: |
HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology. Vol. 4, №2 (2015),  9-9 |
Language: | German |
Document type: | --- |
PDF (Downloads: 3757) |
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
![]() |
|
|
|
![]() |
|
|
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
Social networks: