Studies in Phenomenology



Article/Publication Details
Views: 1994


NEGATIVITY AND QUESTION: ORIGINS OF “WHY-QUESTIONING” IN PHILOSOPHY OF HEIDEGGER

Title in the language of publication: НЕГАТИВНОСТЬ И ВОПРОС: ОСНОВАНИЯ «ПОЧЕМУ-ВОПРОШАНИЯ» В ФИЛОСОФИИ ХАЙДЕГГЕРА
Author: ANTON VAVILOV
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 9, №1 (2020), 256-274
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-1-256-274 PDF (Downloads: 2969)

Abstract
The article constitutes an analysis of the question “why” in its transcendental and existential foundations. Based on Martin Heidegger’s philosophy, this question is shown to be the fundamental question of metaphysics. In his works written after “Being and Time” Heidegger increasingly focused on the “why” question, particularly as regards the inquiry as to “Why there is something rather than Nothing.” The latter constitutes the question of all questions and the key question of philosophizing. According to Heidegger, it is precisely though the capacity of “asking why” that human essence can be explicated. On this issue Heidegger’s fundamental ontology is at variance with Max Scheler’s philosophical anthropology, since “asking why” is more primordial than “saying no” favored by Scheler. However, Heidegger never seems to clarify the relationship between “why?” and “no!”. Therefore, in this article I will try to fill this gap by confronting Scheler with Heidegger as far as the problems of negativity, questioning, metaphysics and human essence are concerned. By reading Scheler’s The Human’s Place in the Cosmos and Heidegger’s What is Metaphysics? as reflections on the origin of metaphysics, one can draw the following conclusions: 1) Orientation to nothing is as fundamental for subjectivity as Scheler’s “saying no”; indeed, the Nothing which nothings gives access to that-what-is and establishes the World as openness. (2) The power of negativity in both cases reveals the strangeness and contingency of being. The fundamental question is made possible by the wonder at the experience of nothingness. (3) Therefore, Heidegger’s “asking why” appears to be derivative from “saying no”. However, in the conclusion I suggest an opposite interpretation based on the foundationless character of Dasein. Thereby “No” becomes possible only based on the permanent “Why” motivated by Dasein’s impossibility to know its own foundation.

Key words
Questioning, negativity, metaphysics, basis, nothing, Dasein, Heidegger, Scheler.

References

  • Agamben, G. (2002). L’aperto. L’uomo e l’animale. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.
  • Agamben, G. (2006). Che cos’è un dispositivo? Roma: Nottetempo.
  • Bataille, G. (1973). La Somme Athéologique. Paris: Gallimard.
  • Derrida, J. (1967). L’écriture et la difference. Paris: Seuil.
  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1986a). Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse. Dritter Teil. Die Philosophie des Geistes. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1986b). Phänomenologie des Geistes. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
  • Heidegger, M. (1976a). Brief über den Humanismus. In Wegmarken (GA 9) (313–364). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1976b). Nachwort zu “Was ist Metaphysik?”. In Wegmarken (GA 9) (303–312). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1976c). Vom Wesen des Grundes. In Wegmarken (GA 9) (123–175). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1976d). Was ist Metaphysik? In Wegmarken (GA 9) (103–122). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1978). Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz (GA 26). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1979). Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (GA 20). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1983a). Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt — Endlichkeit — Einsamkeit (GA 29/30). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1983b). Einführung in die Metaphysik (GA 40). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1986). Seminar in Le Thor 1969. In Seminare (GA 15) (326–371). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1989). Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (GA 24). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1991a). Davoser Disputation zwischen Ernst Cassirer und Martin Heidegger. In Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (GA 3) (274–296). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1991b). Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (GA 3). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1993). Hegel (GA 68). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (1997). Der Deutsche Idealismus (Fichte, Schelling, Hegel) und die philosophische Problemlage der Gegenwart (GA 28). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.
  • Heidegger, M. (2016). Philosophische Anthropologie und Metaphysik des Daseins. In Vorträge (GA 80.1) (213–251). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • Scheler, M. (2016). Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos. Berlin: Hofenberg.
  • Žižek, S. (2000). The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology. London: Verso.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 2867


PHENOMENOLOGY AND SYMBOL: FROM HUSSERL TO BACHELARD

Title in the language of publication: ФЕНОМЕОЛОГИЯ И СИМВОЛ: ОТ ГУССЕРЛЯ К БАШЛЯРУ
Author: BORIS SOKOLOV
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 9, №1 (2020), 235-255
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-1-235-255 PDF (Downloads: 2748)

Abstract
“Blindness” to the problem of the symbol necessarily follows from the main positions of the research strategy of Husserl phenomenology. However, both noema and noesis, as well as the flow of cogitations in our minds are initially infected with symbolism, and therefore the project of phenomenological description needs a “symbolic correction.” The supposed and experienced object is supposed as a symbolically filled object, and the position of the ego describing, constituting, experiencing its object is not only initially infected with cultural symbolism, but also represents the “assemblage point” of any phenomenon as a “constellation” formation. Symbolism is initially “embedded” in any phenomenon and in any scheme of “pure” consciousness. Correspondingly, the flow of phenomena that can be subjected to both noematic and noetic description proceeds according to various “scenarios,” “schemes,” which are nationally and culturally based, and do not follow the single universal route (Past, Present, Future), which is peculiar only to the new European model of time. This drawback of Husserl’s project was overcome in varying degrees by some phenomenologically oriented philosophers. The author of the article analyzes one of such “symbolic adjustments” by reference to the poetic topology (microphenomenology) of poetic image of the Home in the text of French philosopher G. Bachelard.

Key words
Husserl, phenomenology, image, home, symbol, Bachelard, microphenomenology.

References

  • Bachelard, G. (2004). Poetics of Space. In Selected Works: Poetics of Space. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Rossiiskaya politicheskaya entsiklopediya (ROSSPEN) Publ. (In Russian).
  • Deleuze, G. (1995). The Logic of Sense. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Akademiya Publ. (In Russian).
  • Husserl, E. (1994). Collected Works. Vol. I.Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness. Rus. Ed. Moscow: RIG “Logos”, Izdatel’stvo Gnozis Publ. (In Russian).
  • Husserl, E. (1998). Cartesian Meditations. Rus. Ed. St Petersburg: Nauka, Yuventa Publ. (In Russian).
  • Husserl, E. (1999). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Dom intellektual’noi knigi Publ. (In Russian).
  • Cassirer, E. (2002). Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. Vol. 1. Language. Rus. Ed. Moscow, St Petersburg: Universitetskaya kniga Publ. (In Russian).
  • Hook, F. (2015). Breakfast at Sothbey’s: An A — Z of the Art World. Rus. Ed. St Petersburg: Azbuka Publ. (In Russian).
  • Hubner, K. (1996). The Truth of the Myth. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Respublika Publ. (In Russian).
  • Morina, L. P. (2018). A Thing as a Mirror of the Subject of Culture. Studia Culturae, 37 (2018), 36–42. (In Russian).
  • Roel, K. (1911). Versuch einer systematischen Grammatik der Schambala-Schrache. Hamburg: L. Friedrichsen & Co.
  • Shaposhnikova, Y. V., & Shipovalova, L. V. (2018). The Demarcation Problem in the History of Science, or What Historical Epistemology Has to Say About Cultural Identification. Epistemology & Philosophy of Science, 55(1), 52–66. doi: 10.5840/eps20185518. (In Russian).
  • Spengler, O. (1993). The Decline of the West. Vol. I. Form and Actuality. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Mysl’ Publ. (In Russian).

Article/Publication Details
Views: 2262


THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL APPROACH TO QUANTUM MECHANICS: A BETTER UNDERSTANDING OF CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY OF QUANTUM MECHANICS BY REVISITING BOHR AND HUSSERL

Title in the language of publication: THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL APPROACH TO QUANTUM MECHANICS: A BETTER UNDERSTANDING OF CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY OF QUANTUM MECHANICS BY REVISITING BOHR AND HUSSERL
Author: TINA BILBAN
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 9, №1 (2020), 216-234
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-1-216-234 PDF (Downloads: 2806)

Abstract
Niels Bohr, considered one of the fathers of quantum mechanics, formulated a complex interpretation of quantum mechanics that guided his understanding of quantum experiments. The contemporary dispute between realism and anti-realism, the two main approaches to the interpretation of quantum mechanics, is often based on different attitudes towards or even readings of Bohr. We propose that a better understanding of Bohr’s philosophical thought can contribute to the contemporary reconciliation of these opposing philosophical views and thus to a better understanding of the quantum world. Unfortunately, in many contemporary interpretations, Bohr’s philosophical approach to quantum mechanics has been misunderstood, re-interpreted or labelled as ambiguous. This is mostly due to the dispersion of Bohr’s complex and unique interpretation through different texts, never united in a single systematically conceptualized work. To comprehensively explain Bohr’s philosophical approach and his main philosophical concepts, we consider the many similarities between Bohr’s and Husserl’s philosophical approach to science. Husserl developed his philosophical standpoint in a cultural context similar to Bohr’s and shared Bohr’s objects of philosophical consideration as well as his approach to these objects. Parallel reading of Bohr’s and Husserl’s texts reveals the closeness between Bohr’s ontological realism—epistemological anti-realism standpoint and Husserl’s phenomenological standpoint. This explains their similar views on the relationship between mathematical language, scientific method and Nature. While Bohr’s use of the term phenomenon is not equal to Husserl’s, Husserl’s rigorous philosophical explanation of the term helps us to better understand Bohr’s use. Furthermore, the parallel reading facilitates better understanding of one of Bohr’s main philosophical theses, often labelled as ambiguous and interpreted in different ways, that it is necessary to use classical concepts to describe quantum phenomena. We claim that the thesis is connected with the advance of epistemological reconsideration of science at the time of Bohr’s writing. Thus, Bohr considers some parts of argumentation as self-evident, while they are not evident to the contemporary reader. Husserl’s analysis of the relationship between science and the life-world offers a much-needed background for a comprehensive understanding of Bohr’s thesis. The insight into the similarities between Bohr’s and Husserl’s philosophical approach to science and scientific phenomena enables a philosophically rigorous reading of Bohr’s texts; it can eliminate some of the disagreements between realists and anti-realists and provide a firmer philosophical ground for a dialog between them.

Key words
Edmund Husserl, Niels Bohr, phenomenology, phenomena, classical concepts, quantum mechanics, life-world.

References

  • Bohr, N. (1929). The Quantum of Action and the Description of Nature. In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. I (1987) (92–101). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Bohr, N. (1935). Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Reality be Considered Complete? In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. IV (1998) (73–82). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Bohr, N. (1938). Natural Philosophy and Human Cultures. In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. II (1987) (23–31). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Bohr, N. (1946). Newton’s Principles and Modern Atomic Mechanics. In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. IV (1998) (126–131). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Bohr, N.(1954). Unity of Knowledge. In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. II (1987) (67–82). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Bohr, N. (1958). The Rutherford Memorial Lecture. In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. III (1987) (30–73). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Brukner, C., & Zeilinger, A. (2003). Information and Fundamental Elements of the Structure of Quantum Theory. In L. Castell, & O. Ischebeck (Eds.), Time, Quantum, Information (323–354). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935). Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Reality be Considered Complete? Physical Review, 47, 777.
  • Faye, J., & Folse, H. J. (1998). Introduction. In The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. IV (12–13) (1–20). Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
  • Fleck, L. (1935). Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkolektiv. Basel: Benno Schwabe & Co.
  • Føllesdal, D. (2010). The Lebenswelt in Husserl. In D. Hyder, & H. J. Rheinberger (Eds.), Science and the Life-World (27–45). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
  • Fuchs, C. A., & Peres, A. (2000, March 1). Quantum Theory Needs No ‘Interpretation’. Physics Today, 70–71.
  • Heisenberg, W. (1967). Quantum theory and it interpretation. In S. Rozental (Ed.), Niels Bohr: His Life and Work as Seen by his Friends and Colleagues. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
  • Hribar, T. (1997). Phenomenon of the Mind. In Ideje za čisto fenomenologijo in fenomenološko filozofijo. Ljubljana: Slovenska Matica Publ. (In Slovenian).
  • Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil. 1905–1920 (Hua XIII). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology—An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
  • Husserl, E. (1998). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. First book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Lurçat, F. (2007). Understanding Quantum Mechanics with Bohr and Husserl. In L. Boi, P. Kerszberg, & F. Patras, (Eds.), Rediscovering Phenomenology (229–258). Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Merali, Z. (2015). Quantum Physics: What is Really Real. Nature, 521, 7552.
  • Mermin, D. (2004). What’s Wrong With This Quantum World. Physics Today, 57 (2), 10. doi: 10.1063/1.1688051
  • Moran, D., & Cohen, J. (2012). The Husserl Dictionary. London: Continium International.
  • Petersen, A. (1963). Philosophy of Niels Bohr. Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 19(7), 8–14.
  • Timpson, C. G. (2010). Information, Immaterialism, Instrumentalism: Old and New in Quantum Information. In A. Bokulich, & G. Jaeger (Eds.), Philosophy of Quantum Information and Entanglement (208–228). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Zeilinger, A. (1999). A Foundational Principle for Quantum Mechanics. Foundations of Physics, 29, 631–643.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 3203


SOUND ONTOLOGY AND THE BRENTANO-HUSSERL ANALYSIS OF THE CONSCIOUSNESS OF TIME

Title in the language of publication: SOUND ONTOLOGY AND THE BRENTANO-HUSSERL ANALYSIS OF THE CONSCIOUSNESS OF TIME
Author: JORGE LUIS MÉNDEZ-MARTÍNEZ
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 9, №1 (2020), 184-215
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-1-184-215 PDF (Downloads: 3024)

Abstract
Both Franz Brentano and Edmund Husserl addressed sound while trying to explain the inner consciousness of time and gave to it the status of a supporting example. Although their inquiries were not aimed at clarifying in detail the nature of the auditory experience or sounds themselves, they made some interesting observations that can contribute to the current philosophical discussion on sounds. On the other hand, in analytic philosophy, while inquiring the nature of sounds, their location, auditory experience or the audible qualities and so on, the representatives of that trend of thought have remained silent about the depiction of sound and the auditory phenomena in the phenomenological tradition. The paper’s intention is to relate both endeavours, yet the perspective carried out is that of analytic philosophy and, thus, I pay special attention to conceptual analysis as a methodological framework. In this sense, I first explain what sound ontology is in the context of analytic philosophy and the views that it encompasses—namely, the Property View (PV), the Wave View (WV) and the Event View (EV)—. Secondly, I address the problems it entails, emphasising that of sound individuation. In a third section, I propose the possibly controversial conjunction of a “Brentano-Husserl Analysis of the Consciousness of Time” (for short “Brentano-Husserl analysis”) and outline the commonalities of both authors, without ignoring its discrepancies. My main focus is Husserl’s 1905 Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des Inneren Zeitbewusstseins. While addressing the Brentano-Husserl analysis, I elaborate on the problem of temporal and spatial extension (Raumlichkeit and Zeitlichkeit, respectively) of both consciousness and sound. Such comparison is a key one, since after these two developments, one can notice some theoretical movements concerning the shift of attention from sounds to the unity of consciousness, and how they mirror each other. After examining the controversial claims concerning the temporal and spatial extension of both consciousness and sound, I argue in the concluding paragraphs that while considering the accounts of sound ontology, the Brentano-Husserl analysis would probably endorse a Property View and that this could have interesting consequences for the issue of Sound Individuation.

Key words
Sound, auditory experience, Franz Brentano, Edmund Husserl, sound ontology, sound individuation, consciousness of time (Zeitbewusstseins), temporal extension (Zeitlichkeit), spatial extension (Raumlichkeit).

References

  • Abella, M. (2009). Franz Brentano: Unidad de Conciencia y Conciencia del tiempo. Michoacan: Jitanjáfora.
  • Bernet, R. (2009). Husserl’s Early Time-Analysis in Historical Context. Journal of British Society for Phenomenology, 40(2), 117–154.
  • Bernet, R., Kern, I., & Marbach, E. (1996). Edmund Husserl. Darstellung seines Denkens. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
  • Brentano, F. (1995). Descriptive Psychology. London: Routledge.
  • Brentano, F. (2009). Philosophical Investigations on Space, Time and the Continuum. London: Croom Helm.
  • Casati, R., & Dokic, J. (1994). La philosophie du son. Nimes: Chambon.
  • Casati, R., & Dokic, J. (2014). Sounds. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (E. N. Zalta, Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford/archives/fall2014/entries/sounds/
  • Cleland, C. (1991). On the Individuation of Events. Synthese, 86(2), 229–254.
  • Dainton, B. (2017). Temporal Consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (E. N. Zalta, Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford/archives/fall2017/entries/consciousness-temporal/
  • Davis, W. (2005). Concepts and Epistemic Individuation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 290–325.
  • Held, K. (2003). Husserl’s Phenomenology of the Life-World. In D. Welton (Ed.), The New Husserl: A Critical Reader (32–62). Indiana: Indiana University Press.
  • Husserl, E. (1928). Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins. Halle: Max Niemeyer.
  • Husserl, E. (1966). Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1893–1907) (Hua X). The Hague: Martinus Nijhof.
  • Husserl, E. (1973). Ding und Raum. Vorlesungen 1907 (Hua XVI). The Hague: Martinus Nijhof.
  • Husserl, E. (1983). Studien zur Arithmetik und Geometrie. Texte aus dem Nachlass (Hua XXI). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
  • Husserl, E. (2001). Die Bernauer Manuskripte über das Zeitbewusstsein (Hua XXXIII). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Husserl, E. (2004). Wahrnehmung und Aufmerksamkeit (Hua XXXVIII). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Ihde, D. (2007). Listening and Voice, Phenomenologies of Sound. New York: State University of New York Press.
  • Illescas Nájera, M. D. (2012). La vida en la forma del tiempo. Un estudio sobre fenomenología del tiempo en la obra de Edmund Husserl. Michoacán: Jitanjáfora.
  • Kant, I. (1956). Kritik der Reinen Vernunft. Hamburg: Felix Mainer.
  • Kelly, M. (2016). Phenomenology and the Problem of Time. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Kortooms, T. (2002). Phenomenology of Time. Analysis of Time-Consciousness. Dordrecht: Kluwer-Springer.
  • Kraus, O. (1976). Toward a Phenomenology of Time Consciousness. In L. McAlister (Ed.), The Philosophy of Franz Brentano (224–239). London: Duckworth.
  • LeClerc, I. (1979). Concepts of Space. In P. Backscheider (Ed.), Probability, Time, and Space in Eighteenth-Century Literature (209–215). New York: AMS.
  • Lohmar, D. (2010). On the Constitution of the Time of the World: the Emergence of Objective Time on the Ground of Subjective Time. In D. Lohmar, & I. Yamaguchi (Eds.), On Time- New Contributions to the Husserlian Phenomenology of Time (115–136). Cham: Springer.
  • Maclachlan, D. L. C. (1989). The Philosophy of Perception. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
  • Méndez-Martínez, J. L. (2019). What ‘Counts’ as a Sound and How ‘to Count a’ Sound? The Problems of Individuating and Identifying Sounds. Synthesis Philosophica, 67 (1/2019), 173–190.
  • O’Callaghan, C. (2007). Sounds: A Philosophical Theory. London: Oxford University Press.
  • O’Callaghan, C. (2009). Sounds as Events. In M. Nudds, & C. O’Callaghan (Eds.), Sounds and Perception. New Philosophical Essays (26–49). New York: Oxford University Press.
  • O’Callaghan, C. (2014). Auditory Perception. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (E. N. Zalta, Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-auditory/
  • Olbromski, C. J. (2011). The Notion of ‚lebendige Gegenwart‘ as Compliance with the Temporality of the “Now”: The Late Husserl’s Phenomenology of Time. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
  • Pasnau, R. (1999). What is Sound. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49 (196), 309–324.
  • Rollinger, R. P. (1999). Husserl’s Position in the School of Brentano. Dordrecht: Kluwer-Springer.
  • Sartre, J.-P. (1966). La Transcendance de L’ego, esquisse d’une description phénoménologique. Paris: Libraire Philosophique J. Vrin.
  • Scrutton, R. (2009). Sounds as Secondary Objects and Pure Events. In M. Nudds, & C. O’Callaghan (Eds.), Sounds and Perception: New Philosophical Essays (50–68). New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Shim, M. K. (2017). Husserl’s Spatialization of Perceptual Consciousness. In R. Walton, S. Taguchi, & R. Rubio (Eds.), Perception, Affectivity and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology (37–56). Cham: Springer.
  • Simons, P. (1995). Introduction to the 2nd Edition. In F. Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (xiii-xx). London: Routledge.
  • Simons, P. (2015). How to Do Things with Things. In B. Leclercq, S. Richard, & D. Seron (Eds.), Objects and Pseudo-Objects, Ontological Deserts and Jungles from Brentano to Carnap (3–15). Berlin: DeGruyter.
  • Smith, B. (1994). Austrian Philosophy: The Legacy of Franz Brentano. Chicago: Open Court.
  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. London: Routledge.
  • Stumpf, C. (1976). Reminiscences of Brentano. In L. McAlister (Ed.), The Philosophy of Franz Brentano (10–46). London: Duckworth.
  • Summa, M. (2014). Spatio-Temporal Intertwining: Husserl’s Transcendental Aesthetic. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Tarditi, C. (2018). Rethinking Spatiotemporal Extension: Husserl’s Contribution to the Debate on the Continuum Hypothesis. Horizon. Studies in Phenomenology, 7(1), 137–159.
  • Unger, P. (2006). The Problem of the Many. In P. Unger (Ed.), Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2 (113–182). London: Oxford University Press.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 2354


HUSSERL’S CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF TRUTH

Title in the language of publication: HUSSERL’S CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF TRUTH
Author: BENCE PETER MAROSAN
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 9, №1 (2020), 162-183
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-1-162-183 PDF (Downloads: 2794)

Abstract
This article draws attention to certain features of Edmund Husserl’s theory of evidence and truth which, on closer look, reveal how his thoughts on the nature of experience and cognition are current and relevant even in the early 21st century. Many of his contemporaries and subsequent authors considered Husserl to be a late representative of traditional, modernist metaphysics—an idealist, a foundationalist, and an intellectualist, etc. The publication of his vast unpublished manuscripts has evidently dispelled such charges, and a thorough and attentive perusal of his published works (or works prepared for publication) clearly shows how highly problematic such charges were. In the article I aim to highlight the contextualist character of Husserl’s understanding of evidence and truth, of knowledge and Being. Every insight and every entity in his thought fits into a wider context of further experiences, insights, and entities. This conception is manifest at every level of his experience and knowledge: (1) everyday experiences, (2) scientific and (3) philosophical cognition. The evidence at every level is fundamentally open and contextual, and their correlation constitutes an essentially organic reality. With such formulations Husserl says something quite similar to what is now found under the label ‘epistemic contextualism’ in contemporary analytic philosophy. Next to the contextual character of evidence, the second main thesis of my essay is that Husserl’s stance in this question might serve as a fruitful field of dialogue between phenomenology and analytic philosophy.

Key words
Edmund Husserl, non-foundationalism, contextualism, evidence, apodicticity, truth, phenomenological metaphysics.

References

  • Annis, D. (1978). A Contextualist Theory of Epistemic Justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(3), 213–219.
  • Black, T. (2003). Contextualism in Epistemology. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/contextu/
  • Cavallaro, M. (2019). Der Heroismus der Vernunft. Ein Beitrag zur späten Ethik Husserls. In F. Fraisopi (Ed.), Mathesis, Grund, Vernunft: Die philosophische und geistige Identität Europas zwischen Deutschem Idealismus und Phänomenologie.Studien zur Phänomenologie und praktischen Philosophie (147–168). Baden-Baden: Nomos.
  • Cavallaro, M., & Heffernan, G. (Eds.). (2020). The Existential Husserl. A Collection of Critical Essays. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to Be a Fallibilist. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Co.
  • DeRose, K. (2009). The Case for Contextualism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Drummond, J. (1990). Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational Realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Fink, E. (1988). Cartesianische Meditation. Teil I: Die Idee einer transzendentalen Methodelehre. The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The Phenomenological Mind. New York, London: Routledge.
  • Geniusas, S. (2012). The Origins of the Horizon in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Gondek, H. D., & Tengelyi, L. (2011). Neue Phänomenologie in Frankreich. Berlin: Suhrkamp Verlag.
  • Heffernan, G. (1999). A Study in the Sedimented Origins of Evidence: Husserl and His Contemporaries Engaged in a Collective Essay in the Phenomenology and Psychology of Epistemic Justification. Husserl Studies, 16, 83–181.
  • Heffernan, G. (2009). On Husserl’s Remark that „[s]elbst eine sich als apodiktisch ausgebende Evidenz kann sich als Täuschung enthüllen…“ (XVII 164:32–33): Does the Phenomenological Method Yield Any Epistemic Infallibility? Husserl Studies, 25, 15–43.
  • Hermberg, K. (2006). Husserl’s Phenomenology: Knowledge, Objectivity and Others. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group.
  • Hopp, W. (2009). Phenomenology and Falliblity. Husserl Studies, 25, 1–14.
  • Huertas-Jourda, J. (1983). On the Two Foundations of Knowledge According to Husserl. In L.Embree (Ed.), Essays in Memory of Aron Gurwitsch (Current Continental Research, 007) (195–211). Washington: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology and University Press of America.
  • Husserl, E. (1952). Ideen zur einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1956). Erste Philosophie (1923/4). Erste Teil: Kritische Ideengeschichte. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1959). Erste Philosophie (1923/4). Zweiter Teil: Theorie der phänomenologischen Reduktion. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1970a). Philosophie der Arithmetik. Mit ergänzenden Texten (1890–1901). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1970b). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
  • Husserl, E. (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil. 1905–1920. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil. 1929–35. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1973c). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1974). Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1976a). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführungin die reine Phänomenologie 1. Halbband: Text der 1.-3. Auflage — Nachdruck. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1976b). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Teil. Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. In zwei Bänden. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1988). Vorlesungen über Ethik und Wertlehre. 1908–1914. The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1992). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Ergänzungsband. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1934–1937. The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1994a). Briefwechsel. Band II: Die Münchener Phänomenologen. The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1994b). Briefwechsel. Band VI: Philosophenbriefe. The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1994c). Briefwechsel. Band IX: Familienbriefe. The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (1997). Psychological and Transcendental Phenomenology and the Confrontation with Heidegger (1927–1931). The Encylopaedia Britannica Article, the Amsterdam Lectures, “Phenomenology and Anthropology”, and Husserl’s Marginal Notes in Being and Time and Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (2001a). Die ‚Bernauer Manuskripte‘ über das Zeitbewußtsein (1917/18). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Husserl, E. (2001b). Logical Investigations I-II. London & New York: Routledge.
  • Husserl, E. (2006). Späte Texte über Zeitkonstitution (1929–1934). Die C-Manuskripte. New York: Springer.
  • Husserl, E. (2008). Die Lebenswelt. Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer Konstitution. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1916–1937). New York: Springer.
  • Husserl, E. (2014). Grenzprobleme der Phänomenologie. Analysen des Unbewusstseins und der Instinkte. Metaphysik. Späte Ethik (Texte aus dem Nachlass 1908 — 1937). New York: Springer.
  • Lo, L. C. (2008). Die Gottesauffassung in Husserls Phänomenologie. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang Verlag.
  • Lohmar, D. (2008). Kategoriale Anschauung (VI.Logische Untersuchung, §§ 40–66). In V. Mayer, & C. Erhard (Eds.), Edmund Husserl: Logische Untersuchungen (209–237). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
  • Loidolt, S. (2011). Ist Husserls späte Ethik „existenzialistisch“? Überlegungen zu Texten der „Grenzprobleme“ (Hua 42). Journal Phänomenologie, 36, 34–44.
  • Mezei, B. (1995). World and Life-World. Aspects of the Philosophy of Edmund Husserl. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang Verlag.
  • Moran, D. (2002). Introduction to Phenomenology. New York-London: Routledge.
  • Reeder, H. P. (1990). Husserl’s Apodictic Evidence. Southwest Philosophical Studies, 12, 70–78.
  • Ricoeur, P. (1987). Á l’école de la phénoménologie. Paris: Vrin.
  • Rysiew, P. (2016). Epistemic Contextualism. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ contextualism-epistemology/
  • Smith, D. W. (2007). Husserl. London & New York: Routledge.
  • Sokolowski, R. (2008). Husserl’s Discovery of Philosophical Discourse. Husserl Studies, 24, 167–175.
  • Thompson, D. L. (2014). Contextualism Revisited. Retrieved from http://plato.ucs.mun.ca/~davidt/ ContextualismRevisited.pdf
  • Varga, P. A. (2011). The Architectonic and History of Phenomenology. Distinguishing between Fink’s and Husserl’s Notion of Phenomenological Philosophy. In D. Moran, & H. R. Sepp (Eds.), Phenomenology 2010 (4): Selected Essays from Northern Europe (87–114). Bucharest / Paris: Zeta Books / Argos.
  • Williams, M. (1991). Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Williams, M. (1999). Fogelin’s Neo-Pyrrhonism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 7, 141–158.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 2497


NEO-HUSSERLIAN MEDITATIONS: EXTENDING INTENTIONALITY TO THE OBJECTIVE REALM IN FIRST PHENOMENOLOGY

Title in the language of publication: NEO-HUSSERLIAN MEDITATIONS: EXTENDING INTENTIONALITY TO THE OBJECTIVE REALM IN FIRST PHENOMENOLOGY
Author: ADAM LOVASZ
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 9, №1 (2020), 143-161
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-1-143-161 PDF (Downloads: 2756)

Abstract
I seek here to return to the original spirit of Edmund Husserl’s “radicalism.” To be radical means to be both rooted in a tradition and to retrace a path back to one’s roots. According to the position I advocate, phenomenology may be reconceived of as an enterprise in realism. Through a creative rereading of one of phenomenology’s founding texts, Husserl’s Cartesian Meditations, I suggest that phenomenology can indeed provide us with a semantics applicable to realist ontologies, provided we excise phenomenological concepts from their subjectivist framework, providing a new structure with which to analyze reality. Specifically, Husserl’s eidetic Apriori may be reconceived as denoting the inherent dynamism of existents. Movement would be the basis of manifestation, a universal category unconditioned in itself. That which appears need not be synonymous with all that which is given to experience. The eidos is the manifold of coiled movements awaiting manifestation, whilst the a priori is movement in itself. Following Graham Harman’s lead, I expand the scope of the Husserlian idea of intentionality, reconceptualizing it as the directionality pertaining to any process whatsoever. Following Jaakko Hintikka, I take the cogito to be nothing other than performativity in its emergent state. Several different phenomenal horizons can connect to the same type of intentionality. The nonlinear nature of temporality means that even radically distant horizons are capable of sharing in the same intentionality. Once reenvisioned as a “genuine universal ontology” (this is Husserl’s expression), phenomenological semantics can be extended to include any and all types of existents. First phenomenology need not maintain the primacy of perception or subjectivity.

Key words
Eidos, Graham Harman, Edmund Husserl, intentionality, phenomenology, realism, speculative realism.

References

  • Auberlen, C. A. (1847). Die Theosophie Friedrich Christoph Oetingers nach ihren Grundzügen. Ein Beitrag zur Dogmengeschichte und zur Geschichte der Philosophie. Tübingen: L. Fr. Fues.
  • Derrida, J. (2005). Writing and Difference. London/New York: Routledge.
  • Di Bernardo, A., Millo, O., Barbone, M., Alpern, H., Kalcheim, Y., Sassi, U., … Robinson, J. W. A. (2017). P-wave Triggered Superconductivity in Single-Layer Graphene on an Electron-Doped Oxide Superconductor. Nature Communications, 1–9.
  • Harman, G. (2011). The Quadruple Object. Winchester/Washington: Zero Books.
  • Harman, G. (2005). Guerrilla Metaphysics. Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things. La Salle/Chicago: Open Court.
  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Cogito, ergo sum: Inference or Performance? The Philosophical Review, 71(1), 3–32.
  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Magliola, R. (1997) On Deconstructing Life-Worlds. Buddhism, Christianity, Culture. Atlanta: Scholars Press.
  • Moran, D. (2000). Introduction to Phenomenology. London, New York: Routledge.
  • Schmidt, G. A., & Frank, A. (2018). The Silurian Hypothesis: Would It Be Possible to Detect an Industrial Civilization in the Geological Record? International Journal of Astrobiology, 18 (2), 1–9.
  • Smith, A. D. (2003). Husserl and the Cartesian Meditations. London, New York: Routledge.
  • Stump, A. D., Sperling, F. A. H., & Scriber, J. M. (2003). Gene Flow Between Great Lakes Region Populations of the Canadian Tiger Swallowtail Butterfly, ‘Papilio Canadensis,’ Near the Hybrid Zone with P. Glaucus (Lepidoptera: Papilionidae). The Great Lakes Entomologist, 36(1–2), 41–53.
  • Tørring, T., Voigt, N. V., Nangreave, J., Yan, H., & Gothelf, K. V. (2011). DNA Origami: a Quantum Leap for Self-Assembly of Complex Structures. Chemical Society Reviews, 40(12), 5636–5646.