Studies in Phenomenology



Article/Publication Details
Views: 3346


PHENOMENOLOGY AND BEING-IN-ITSELF IN HARTMANN’S ONTOLOGY: LAYING THE FOUNDATIONS

Title in the language of publication: PHENOMENOLOGY AND BEING-IN-ITSELF IN HARTMANN’S ONTOLOGY: LAYING THE FOUNDATIONS
Author: KEITH R. PETERSON
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 8, №1 (2019),  33-51
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2019-8-1-33-51 PDF (Downloads: 2728)

Abstract
Was Nicolai Hartmann a phenomenologist? Answering this question has become more important in the context of debates over new realisms in Continental philosophy. To answer it, the paper highlights five important points. First, Hartmann’s own distinction between the phenomenological school of thought and phenomenological method must be preserved. He does not accept the sweeping humanistic opposition between the sciences and phenomenology, and yet (like the phenomenologists) he employs a method that aims to provide a description of phenomena following on a suspension of metaphysical commitments that is directed at their essential structures, with some important qualifications. Secondly, he rejects the phenomenological reduction because it identifies the natural attitude with a metaphysical standpoint and it advocates instead a ‘naïve consciousness’ free of metaphysical assumptions. Thirdly, his assessment of phenomenology is conditioned by his conception of cognition as a transcendent act. He finds that phenomenology fails to adequately account for the whole phenomenon of cognition, especially its characteristic grasp of something independent of the act. Fourthly, Hartmann grants the irreducibility of phenomena, but holds that they are characteristically unstable, referring to something beyond themselves and forcing us to decide whether what they show is genuine or not. There is thus no infallible intuition of phenomena. Finally, from an epistemological perspective, the concept being-in-itself is merely a counterpart to the concept of the phenomenon, which we do not need for the purposes of ontology. Based on this reassessment, it is concluded that Hartmann employs some form of the phenomenological method but cannot be identified as a phenomenologist.

Key words
Nicolai Hartmann, phenomenology, being-in-itself, cognition, phenomenological method, transcendent act, phenomenal transcendence, natural attitude, natural realism, metaphysics.

References

  • Hartmann, N. (1949). Grundzüge einer Metaphysik der Erkenntnis. Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Hartmann, N. (1965). Zur Grundlegung der Ontologie. Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Hartmann, N. (2014). Diesseits von Idealismus und Realismus. In G. Hartung & M. Wunsch (Eds.), Nicolai Hartmann: Studien zur neuen Ontologie und Anthropologie (15-64). Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Hartmann, N. (2017). The Megarian and the Aristotelian Concept of Possibility: A Contribution to the History of the Ontological Problem of Modality. Axiomathes, 27 (2), 209-223.
  • Husserl, E. (1960). Phenomenology. In R. M. Chisholm (Ed.), Realism and the Background of Phenomenology (118-128). Glencoe, Illinois: The Free Press.
  • Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Meillassoux, Q. (2014). Time Without Becoming. In A. Longo (Ed.), Time Without Becoming. Middlesex: Mimesis International.
  • Möckel, C. (2012). Nicolai Hartmann — ein Phänomenologe? Zu den Termini Phänomen und Phänomenologie. In G. Hartung, C. Strube & M. Wunsch (Eds.), Von der Systemphilosophie zur systematischen Philosophie: Nicolai Hartmann (105-127). Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Sparrow, T. (2014). The End of Phenomenology: Metaphysics and the New Realism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
  • Spiegelberg, H. (1960). The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction. Volume 1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.