Studies in Phenomenology



Article/Publication Details
Views: 3449


NEW WAYS TO TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY:
WHY EPISTEMOLOGY MUST BE A DESCRIPTIVE AND EIDETIC STUDY OF CONSCIOUSNESS

Title in the language of publication: NEW WAYS TO TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY:
WHY EPISTEMOLOGY MUST BE A DESCRIPTIVE AND EIDETIC STUDY OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Author: Philipp Berghofer
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 7, №1 (2018),  121-136
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2018-7-1-121-136 PDF (Downloads: 2869)

Abstract
Husserl has spilled much ink motivating the transcendental reduction that is supposed to pave the way for the ultimate, subjective science, i.e., transcendental phenomenology. However, Husserl’s original ways to the transcendental reduction are problematic. One such issue concerns the (in)fallibility of apodictic evidence. If apodictic evidence must be infallible, the project of transcendental phenomenology seems to be unattainable. However, if apodictic evidence is fallible, the project of transcendental phenomenology is not as well-motivated as seemingly implied by Husserl’s Cartesian way. In the present paper, I put forward new ways to transcendental phenomenology that are based on arguments in current analytic epistemology. I show that the new evil demon problem, Laurence BonJour’s example of clairvoyance, and the phenomenon of blindsight can not only be used to make a case against reliabilism, but also to motivate the core ideas of transcendental phenomenology. The underlying conviction of this paper is that any argument or line of reasoning that, for epistemological reasons, motivates the study of consciousness in a non-empirical descriptive and eidetic fashion can be considered a way to transcendental phenomenology. The thesis of this paper is that one such way to transcendental phenomenology can be found by engaging in current epistemological debates. I exemplify this new way to the reduction by discussing concrete problems, putting particular emphasis on the new evil demon problem as it allows us to motivate a phenomenological version of epistemic internalism, according to which two experiences that are phenomenologically identical are also justificationally identical, which means that they justify the same beliefs to the same degree.

Key words
Transcendental phenomenology, epistemology, Husserl, transcendental reduction, phenomenological epistemology.

References

  • Berghofer, P. (2018a). Husserl’s Conception of Experiential Justification: What It Is and Why It Matters. Husserl Studies, 1-26. doi: 10.1007/s10743-018-9225-8
  • Berghofer, P. (2018b). Towards a Phenomenological Conception of Experiential Justification. Synthese, 1–29. doi: 10.1007/s11229-018-1744-5
  • BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5 (1), 53-73.
  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • David, M. (2014). Truth as the Primary Epistemic Goal: A Working Hypothesis. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (363-377). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Drummond, J. (1975). Husserl on the Ways to the Performance of the Reduction. Man and World, 8 (1), 47-69.
  • Ghijsen, H. (2016). The Puzzle of Perceptual Justification. Switzerland: Springer.
  • Heffernan, G. (2009). On Husserl’s Remark That „[s]elbst eine sich als apodiktisch ausgebende Evidenz kann sich als Täuschung enthüllen ...“ (XVII 164:32-33): Does the Phenomenological Method Yield Any Epistemic Infallibility? Husserl Studies, 25, 15-43.
  • Hopp, W. (2009). Phenomenology and Fallibility. Husserl Studies, 25 (1), 1-14.
  • Hopp, W. (2013). Replies. Husserl Studies, 29 (1), 65-77.
  • Hopp, W. (2016). Phenomenal Conservatism and the Principle of All Principles. In D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, & W. Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology (180-202). New York: Routledge.
  • Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesianische Mediatationen und Pariser Vorträge (Hua I). The Hague: Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1974). Formale und transzendentale Logik (Hua XVII). The Hague: Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, Erstes Buch, Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie (Hua III-1). The Hague: Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1984). Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie. Vorlesungen 1906/07 (Hua XXIV). Dordrecht: Nijhoff
  • Husserl, E. (1987). Aufsätze und Vorträge (Hua XXV). Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (2000). Londoner Vorträge. Husserl Studies, 16, 183-254.
  • Husserl, E. (2002). Logische Untersuchungen. Ergänzungsband. Erster Teil. Entwürfe zur Umarbeitung der VI. Untersuchung und zur Vorrede für die Neuauflage der Logischen Untersuchungen (Sommer 1913) (Hua XX-1). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Husserl, E. (2008). Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge: Lectures 1906/07. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Lehrer, K., & Cohen, S. (1983). Justification, Truth, and Coherence. Synthese, 55 (2), 191-207.
  • Luft, S. (2004). Husserl’s Phenomenological Reduction Revisited: An Attempt of a Renewed Account. Anuario Filosofico, 37 (1), 65-104.
  • Pietersma, H. (2000). Phenomenological Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Pritchard, D. (2011). Evidentialism, Internalism, Disjunctivism. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its Discontents (235-253). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Rinofner-Kreidl, S. (2013). Mental Contents, Transparency, Realism: News from the Phenomenological Camp. Husserl Studies, 29 (1), 33-50.
  • Smithies, D. (2014). The Phenomenal Basis of Epistemic Justification. In M. Sprevak & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mind (98-124). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Tucker, C. (2010). Why Open-Minded People Should Endorse Dogmatism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 529-545.
  • Williamson, T. (2005). Replies to Commentators. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 468-491.
  • Wiltsche, H. (2015). Intuitions, Seemings, and Phenomenology. Teorema, 34 (3), 57-77.